Monday, February 18, 2008

Desires with Presuppositions

Kris McDaniel and Ben Bradley have a great article, 'Desires' (forthcoming in Mind), which argues that desire is a three-place relation between a person and two propositions: the object of the desire, and the condition on its applicability. (Though for ordinary unconditional desires, this is a mere technicality: the condition is the trivial proposition that any old thing is the case.)

This is motivated by the thought that some desires are neither satisfied nor frustrated, but simply cancelled (or inapplicable). Consider a child's desire for Santa to have a nice Christmas, or my desire to have an icecream later if I still feel like it. Even if these things never come about, it doesn't necessarily seem as though my past desire was thwarted. (Ask my earlier self: "Do you desire that, even if your future self no longer feels like it, you still get the icecream anyway?" I will answer, "of course not!") The desires come with certain presuppositions: that Santa exists, or that I will continue to want icecream, etc. When those conditions fail, the desire simply no longer applies.

McDaniel and Bradley compare their view to Strawson's suggestion about non-referring expressions: "the question whether his statement ['the king of France is wise'] was true or false simply didn't arise, because there is no such person as the king of France." So it goes, I suppose, for the person who desires that the king of France be wise. The question whether their desire is fulfilled or frustrated simply doesn't arise. To further illustrate, the authors suggest that conditional desires are like conditional bets: if the condition isn't met, you neither win nor lose; instead, the bet is off.

How should a utilitarian take cancelled desires to figure in the calculus? The obvious option is that cancelled desires have no normative significance, whereas fulfilled desires have positive value, and thwarted desires have disvalue. So if we can find a desire the thwarting of which doesn't matter in the slightest, that might be taken to show that it's a conditional desire which has been cancelled.

One thing I disagree with: the authors claim that ordinary desires (e.g. for Bob to be happy) are conditional on their not having terrible consequences (e.g. a billion deaths). But that just seems false to me. I still want Bob to be happy, it's just that I want to avoid a billion deaths even more. The former desire is outweighed, not cancelled. (One might restrict the term 'desire' to non-outweighed or 'all things considered' desires; but I can't imagine why we'd want to. I'm still going to lament Bob's unhappiness; this is importantly different from my cancelled desire for icecream.)

In general, I think it is tempting to over-apply the conditional apparatus. In class, someone suggested the example of a desire for tea on the condition that there's sugar. But this is more plausibly seen as an unconditional desire for tea and sugar. The absence of sugar doesn't cancel the desire, it thwarts it. (Again, the test is to ask whether lacking the object of the desire is in some sense bad from the perspective of the person with the desire.)

One thing I'm unclear on is precisely how a conditional desire (for P given Q) differs from the preference for (Q&P) > (Q&~P). The authors suggest that the conditional desire implies the preference, but not vice versa. Let Q be that you crave chocolate, and P be that you eat chocolate. If you are stuck craving chocolate, it's certainly preferable that you get to have some. You should have the above preference, then. But this needn't imply any actual desire - even conditionally - for chocolate. That sounds right, but then what more is required for desire, exactly? (Not a desire for the condition to obtain, else it might as well be an unconditional desire for P & Q.) Some current pro-attitude towards the object, perhaps? This just seems a little unclear to me.

4 comments:

  1. Hey Richard,

    Thanks for the attention to and praise for our paper! Here are a couple of replies.

    (1) About Bob and the catastrophe: yeah, the outweighing story seems better there. We tried to qualify our application of the cancelling idea in section 10.

    (2) What's the extra bit that you need to have a desire rather than just a preference? It's hard to say exactly, but more than just a pro-attitude. It's something "warmer": something with more pull to it, like an urge. On our view, preferences can result from urges, aversions, likes, value judgments, and lots of other things. It's the other things that are the fundamental mental states, not the preferences.

    Does this help?

    Ben

    ReplyDelete
  2. In your last example, I think the difference between the conditional desire and the preference is that the preference is self-referential. You are essentially saying that you would prefer to have chocolate if you crave it but would not want to crave chocolate if you do not have it. So you are not expressing a desire but a preference based on possible desires.

    In another example let 'P' be 'die quickly' and 'Q' be 'have an extremely painful disease that would kill me slowly.'

    I might prefer to have the disease and die quickly than to have the disease and not die quickly. But I do not think it is correct to say that I have a desire to die quickly, but rather just a desire not to suffer from the disease. But I guess it's semantics.

    I'm going to post about it on my Philosophy Forums. Thanks!

    ReplyDelete
  3. Hi Ben, thanks for commenting! Your "something warmer" suggestion sounds quite natural. But in light of Scott's "semantics" comment, and my latest post, do you think this difference has any normative significance?

    ReplyDelete
  4. Here's a thought: a preference for (Q and P) over (Q and not-P) doesn't tell us how this compares to the default of (neither Q nor P). Perhaps a conditional desire for P given Q implies that you'd prefer the desire to be satisfied than cancelled?

    This would seem the best approach if we are interested in a normative (rather than intuitive) theory of desire.

    ReplyDelete

Visitors: check my comments policy first.
Non-Blogger users: If the comment form isn't working for you, email me your comment and I can post it on your behalf. (If your comment is too long, first try breaking it into two parts.)

Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.